CHAPTER 6
Human Sociobiology
Given the scope of the polemic unleashed by human sociobiology in recent years, no one can enter this arena without some trepidation. It is a minefield because of the complexity of the biological questions involved and because application of powerful biological models to the study of human behavior simultaneously creates theoretical, political, and ethical difficulties. Precisely because this particular subject attracts so much attention, it is reasonable to believe that it touches directly on fundamental ways in which we conceptualize the relationship between nature and culture.
E. O. Wilson’s Sociobiology: The New Synthesis (1975), a quasi-textbook modeled in important ways on Darwin’s Origin of Species, gave the field its public identity and set the boundaries of the current debate. That its sophistication in certain areas has been quickly surpassed is not an argument against its general significance. Such a book does not have a great impact simply because of the force of the ideas presented; they must be presented in an order and context that are themselves compelling. Sociobiology is a compelling work in this sense.
In On Human Nature (1978) Wilson attempts to address his critics and to expand the arguments advanced in Sociobiology. Wilson and Charles Lumsden’s Genes, Mind, and Culture (Lumsden and Wilson 1981) attempts to specify the theoretical framework supposed to be implicit in On Human Nature. Though it makes certain points from the previous books clearer, it does not fundamentally alter the structure of Wilson’s discourse on the relationship between nature and culture.
There is no doubt that sociobiology has an important contribution to make to evolutionary biology as a whole, no matter what the verdict about human sociobiology is. Ever since Darwin’s Origin of Species there has been a recognized need for an evolutionary analysis of social behavior. Observations across wide ranges of species show that certain forms of self-sacrificing behavior are common in the animal world and are often advantageous to the fitness of the collectivity though they necessarily reduce the fitness of the sacrificing individuals. By evolutionary logic, such individuals would be less and less represented in populations over time, and this kind of collectively useful behavior would disappear.
Darwin himself was aware of this problem, as his statements on neuter and sterile groups within a species demonstrate. Solutions to it were not forthcoming. It resurfaced with considerable impact when V. C. Wynne-Edwards published his Animal Dispersion in Relation to Social Behaviour in 1962. He claimed that somehow individuals sacrificed themselves for the benefit of the group and he organized an array of evidence to support this view.
Wynne-Edwards’ book was subjected to a detailed critique by G. C. Williams (1966), who found all of Wynne-Edwards’ data wanting. In 1964 W. D. Hamilton published the first of a series of papers that attempted to reconcile the individualism of selection with the preservation of certain behaviors beneficial to the group at the expense of the individual (Hamilton 1964, 1970, 1971a, 1971b). This effort resulted in the creation of the concept of “inclusive fitness.” Wilson succinctly renders it as “the sum of an individual’s own fitness plus the sum of all the effects it causes to the related parts of the fitnesses of all its relatives” (Wilson 1975:118).
This seemingly simple concept accounts for the emergence of sociobiology. It argues that socially beneficial behavior can develop and be maintained in populations by evolutionary processes already understood, without need to invoke some vague notion of group selection. To the extent that certain behavior is beneficial to other members of the group closely related to the individual who exhibits such behavior, acts of self-sacrifice can make evolutionary sense. So long as the benefits that related group members derive exceed the costs to the individual, the behavior increases fitness.
To be sure, operationalization of this set of notions is extremely difficult. These practical problems have brought considerable refinement in the formulation of the arguments. But the fact remains that the concept of kin selection attempts to resolve a major problem that had blocked the application of evolutionary principles to the analysis of social behavior. Whether or not the idea must ultimately be reformulated, its importance cannot be questioned.
Application of sociobiological arguments to the study of humans, as well as to other social species, is not some diabolical ploy, the excesses of certain practitioners notwithstanding. This important new development in biological science is relevant to at least some social species and it is reasonable to entertain possible applications to humans. If arguments thus far advanced in regard to humans cannot be taken very seriously, they do not invalidate the enterprise.
No one should underestimate the harsh empirical requirements to be met in such an analysis. We need past and present population sizes; complete, accurate pedigrees; random mating system (unless the form of many sociobiological propositions is changed considerably); and typologies of “fitness-enhancing reciprocities,” along with concrete data about their reproductive effects. While all evolutionary research involves empirical compromises that fall far short of perfection, compelling samples of data on these points are minimum requirements to be met before anyone can say that data exist to support or disprove the stronger sociobiological propositions as applied to humans. That such evidence has been less the center of attention than adaptive storytelling (pro and con) is part of the ambivalence surrounding sociobiology that needs to be unraveled.
The central question I ask of Wilson’s work is whether or not he applies any particular element of specifically sociobiological theory to humans. The answer is no. Wilson’s views on humans have not profited from the intriguing propositions sociobiology could generate. What he says about humans was said not only before sociobiology came about but before evolutionary biology as a whole. Nor is this some personal peculiarity of Wilson’s thought. In conceptualizing human nature, Wilson unknowingly reproduces a pre-evolutionary view of the relationship between nature and culture, thus failing to apply evolutionary analysis to human behavior and demonstrating the pervasive power of cultural systems.
Sociobiology: The New Synthesis
Morality, Selfishness, Altruism, and Kinship
Sociobiology’s first chapter, “The Morality of the Gene,” begins by taking issue with Albert Camus’s statement that suicide is the only important philosophical question. It is the biologist, Wilson claims,
who is concerned with questions of physiology and evolutionary history, [who] realizes that self-knowledge is constrained and shaped by the emotional control centers in the hypothalamus and limbic system of the brain. These centers flood our consciousness with all the emotions… that are consulted by ethical philosophers who wish to intuit the standards of good and evil. What… made the hypothalamus and limbic system? They evolved by natural selection.… This brings us to the central theoretical problem of sociobiology: how can altruism, which by definition reduces personal fitness, possibly evolve by natural selection? The answer is kinship. [Wilson 1975:3]
Then by a leap that has not worked for anyone, Wilson implies that understanding the material structure of the brain and the evolutionary process by which it came into being creates direct understanding of the content of human thought. We can adjudicate, he implies, between particular thoughts (in this case life versus suicide) by reference to biological structures and their evolution. This theme persists in his other works as well.
While the necessary material structure of the human brain does in an ultimate sense constrain what can be thought, these constraints relate so remotely to our ability to predict the content and structure of systems of ideas that Wilson’s formulation cannot be taken seriously. Almost no one who accepts evolutionary theory will dispute the point that the hypothalmic and limbic systems evolved by natural selection or that we must learn why altruism is evolutionarily possible. But this knowledge will not automatically lead us to moral clarity.
Wilson’s prose suggests that selfishness and altruism exist in a pitched battle, though nothing in the theory of inclusive fitness suggests that they must. He evokes an image of humanity torn between ambivalent impulses programmed into our brains and argues that understanding the conditions that led to this impasse will permit us to control our behavior. This is an optimistic view of the human condition with strong Freudian overtones. Nothing in it is entailed in the theory of inclusive fitness.
These very first paragraphs show something about Wilson’s use of words that will compound confusion later on. “Morality,” “selfishness,” “altruism,” and “kinship” are all words that directly imply a cultural capacity for abstract thought, for deliberative behavior. Wilson’s use of terms taken from the cultural world humanizes the nonhuman world by imputing morality, selfishness, altruism, and kinship to cultureless creatures. Then by reverse extrapolation he applies these terms to humans. It then appears that we are just like all the other animals. This is just linguistic sleight-of-hand, a point Marshall Sahlins (1976) has made eloquently. That we are animals no one can doubt. That we are just like any other animal is less clear. We are biocultural animals—not nobler or better, but different.
From Nature Through Mind to Culture
These early pages set the baseline for Wilson’s whole argument about the relationship between genes, mind, and culture. His reductive program for eliminating the distance between culture and biology operates by rhetorical means that have little or nothing to do with sociobiological theory proper. Even Wilson does not follow his reductionism: he holds “rationality” to be above the realm of direct biological causation, while making it crucial to our species’ biological salvation.
A highly social species such as man “knows,” or more precisely it has been programmed to perform as if it knows, that its underlying genes will be proliferated maximally only if it orchestrates behavioral responses that bring into play an efficient mixture of personal survival, reproduction, and altruism. Consequently … the conscious mind [is taxed] with ambivalences whenever the organisms encounter stressful situations. [P. 4]
The mind is simply a complex apparatus that overlies the genes and must necessarily act in the interest of perpetuating the genes of that organism. The mind is a fitness-informing device. In this way Wilson drives a wedge between the genes as an ultimate level of reality and the conscious mind as an environmental tracking device that calculates fitness outcomes of various courses of action.
Chapter 2 begins in a striking way with the following lines: “Genes, like Leibnitz’s monads, have no windows; the higher properties of life are emergent” (p. 7). Here is an interesting conundrum. Much of the book argues that genetic causality is the only form of “real” biological causality. Yet here a combined argument for holism and emergent levels of organization is made the centerpiece. Wilson wants to use two incompatible views of the organization of the world as they suit his convenience.
Sociobiology is the study of the biological foundations of all social behavior. As genes underlie the mind, so sociobiology supposedly underlies sociology and the humanities. “It may not be too much to say that sociology and the other social sciences, as well as the humanities, are the last branches of biology waiting to be included in the Modern Synthesis” (p. 4). This remark threatens many territories and has been widely cited. Wilson claims to recognize no general causes of behavior that are not biological, and so the incorporation of the social sciences and humanities in the sociobiological synthesis will be accomplished according to the ground rules of biology. While this idea in itself is not bad, since nothing in the social sciences and humanities could in any ultimate sense conflict with the biological capacities of human beings, Wilson’s terms of incorporation destroy rather than explain the social sciences and the humanities.
Wilson defines society as “a group of individuals belonging to the same species and organized in a cooperative manner” (p. 7). This vague and analytically useless definition of society is purposely broad, Wilson says, so that it can apply to almost any aggregation of a species in which some small degree of interaction occurs. In fact, this vagueness does not seem costly at the outset, but it becomes so when the similarities and differences in the social forms of different species and ultimately in human and other animal societies are examined.
Wilson provides an elaborate discussion of various mechanisms and effects related to the rate of the evolution of social behavior. He endeavors to develop a concept of “social drift,” made up of a genetic element and a “tradition” element, in analogy to genetic drift. As an example of “tradition drift,” defined as behaviors learned solely as a result of social experience, he speaks of the acceptance of a new idea in a human group. His model, which is a very old one, claims that ideas compete for acceptance, and the best variant survives.1
We can see here the weakness of Wilson’s approach to cultural analysis. The mechanistic treatment of ideas apart from their content and contexts is inexcusable. Further, the modality for communicating ideas between parent and child and among cohorts is linguistic communication, a system of transmission dependent on distinctive cultural mechanisms. The acceptance or rejection of an idea is as significantly conditioned by its fit within a larger system of ideas and by the modes in which it is communicated as by any inherent strength or weakness in the idea itself.
Though the concept of tradition drift has something to recommend it, especially as applied to nonhuman animals (whose social learning has been underemphasized by scholars until recently), the application to humans reveals important weaknesses in Wilson’s thinking. He abstracts out a prime characteristic of culture, but in the process he impoverishes the concept of culture beyond recognition. It is abundantly clear that he does not use the concept “symbol,” “symbolic system,” “context,” or “meaning” in acceptable ways. These weaknesses ultimately ruin his discussion of humans.
Speaking of group size in an evolutionary context, Wilson uses the example of the Mennonites in the rural United States as proof that mechanisms found in other animal societies work for humans. This choice is quite revealing. Not only are the demographic data adduced very weak, but he forgets that the boundaries of Mennonite communities are religiously defined. Yet the fluctuation he finds in Mennonite group size is said to represent the operation of universal mechanisms. How many macaque communities are bounded religiously and are ethnically oppressed? More important, Wilson’s inclusion of the Mennonites does not enhance our understanding of them at all because it is already known that communal agricultural societies have an optimum size that varies according to changes in land base, technology, and communication. How does the use of evolutionary language improve our understanding of either the Mennonites or the macaques? If this is what Wilson means when he says that human behavior is “consistent” with sociobiological theory, then I see no difference between “weak” inferences and useless ones.
Wilson also misses opportunities to apply his models to humans well. When he discusses adjustable group size and describes societies that adjust their size to available resources, he does not mention humans. This is one subject on which there is somewhat better human evidence (Lee and De Vore, eds., 1968). It appears that cultural systems are great facilitators of the expansion and contraction of group sizes and that kinship networks (in the correct anthropological sense of the term “kinship”) serve to enhance the ability of groups to fuse and divide. Here, where a human example would be worth thinking about, Wilson overlooks the opportunity.
Later, after arguing that the correct definition of higher organisms is the degree of refinement in their ability to adjust to the environment (p. 151), he takes up tradition once again. “The highest form of tradition … is of course human culture. But culture aside from its involvement with language, which is truly unique, differs from animal tradition only in degree” (p. 168; emphasis mine). This statement is quite remarkable. Wilson uses a radical distinction here between humans and animals, yet presumably a major point of the book is to moderate just such a distinction.
The phrase “culture aside from its involvement with language” is incomprehensible. Ordinarily we define culture as a congeries of symbolically mediated behaviors that have some systematic internal organization. In the social sciences and the humanities we have often considered language a major paradigm for what culture in general is like. There is also wide agreement that the development of language is the key to the development of culture; that without one the other cannot exist. And finally, the absolute uniqueness of human language itself is being questioned by the very ethologists from whom Wilson otherwise draws so much sustenance. What, then, can Wilson mean? Unfortunately, the only interpretation that can be placed on this crucial passage is that Wilson does not know what he means by either “culture” or “language.”
The chapters on communication support this contention. Though Wilson tries to use language as paradigmatic for communication systems (p. 177), he rejects the universal design features of language, is confused about phonemes, and entirely forgets that language is not analyzable without reference to meaning. And then, having used language as a paradigm for communication system in general, he reverses the field and argues that human language is unique (pp. 201–2) and that the application of human language concepts to other animal communication systems is risky.
In part, Wilson’s problem is simply one of expertise. The material on aggression, spacing, and dominance is better handled. He retains a lively sense of multiple causes and multiple effects and he balances predictive statements with reasonable caution. Here he is clearly on familiar ground. Except for one careless aside on “obvious parallels” with humans in his discussion of the will to power (p. 287), this set of chapters, in which all sorts of bits and pieces of human evidence are fitted in, is not marred by the kind of outlandish comparisons that came earlier. Knowing this material better, Wilson is more diffident about extrapolation.
After a discussion of what he terms “role” and “caste” among nonhuman animals, Wilson turns to human roles.
But whereas, social organization in the insect colonies depends on programmed, altruistic behavior by an ergonomically optimal mix of castes, the welfare of human societies is based on trade-offs among individuals playing roles. When too many human beings enter one occupation, their personal cost-to-benefit ratios rise, and some individuals transfer to less crowded fields for selfish reasons. [P. 313]
This statement could have been made by Galton, Malthus, or Milton Friedman. It reveals a naive free-competition model of society without any awareness of problems of social stratification and power or of the long history of debate on this subject.
Species Immortality
Since modification of the environment is a particularly marked human characteristic, Wilson’s comments on this subject have considerable importance.
Manipulation of the physical environment is the ultimate adaptation. If it were somehow brought to perfection, environmental control would insure the indefinite survival of the species, because the genetic structure could at last be matched precisely to favorable conditions and freed from the capricious emergencies that endanger its survival. No species has approached to environmental control, not even man. [Pp. 59–60; emphasis mine]
This statement needs to be remembered, for it contains the core of Wilson’s peculiar utopianism. If we humans could manipulate the environment rather than letting it affect us, we could become our own ultimate causes in the world. And were we so inclined—as Wilson seems to be—we could try to bring evolution as we know it to a halt. This goal is nothing less than the achievement of species immortality in the material world. It is Wilson’s alternative to the immortality of the individual soul.
Scholarly emphasis on human manipulation of the physical environment has led many authors to argue that culture has taken over from biology among humans. Wilson does not agree. He calls such manipulation an “adaptation,” thus insisting that culture be treated as one more biological adaptation. While this position is generally reasonable, Wilson finds it necessary to ignore the symbolic and systemic aspects of culture.
Why does Wilson consistently ignore these aspects? I believe it is because he sees culture (in contrast with science) as obscuring our view of truth. Only when we purge culture of its irrational elements will culture give a true picture of the environment. Then we can reach the ultimate adaptation. Wilson thus wishes to reduce culture to its scientific-rational components. The rest of culture must be consigned to the dustbin.
“Man: From Sociobiology to Sociology”
Wilson has been repeatedly drubbed for his final chapter. Indeed, he published On Human Nature to remedy just this problem. But the errors in this chapter merit comment because they help to reveal the major cultural presuppositions that underlie Wilson’s failure to apply evolutionary analysis to humans. All the difficulties discussed earlier now combine and interact.
The chapter begins with an invocation of an extraterrestrial zoologist, presumably because from an extraterrestrial perspective we humans could not deny that we are animals. Noting that we are ecologically “peculiar” because we are so wide ranging and locally dense in some areas, Wilson also stresses our anatomical uniqueness.
We have leaped forward in mental evolution in a way that continues to defy self-analysis. The mental hypertrophy has distorted even the most basic primate social qualities into nearly unrecognizable forms. Individual species of Old World monkeys and apes have notably plastic social organizations; man has extended the trend into a protean ethnicity. Monkeys and apes utilize behavioral scaling to adjust aggressive and sexual interactions; in man the scales have become multidimensional, culturally adjustable, and almost endlessly subtle. Bonding and the practices of reciprocal altruism are rudimentary in other primates; man has expanded them into great networks where individuals consciously alter roles from hour to hour as if changing masks. It is the task of comparative sociobiology to trace these and other human qualities as closely as possible back through time. Besides adding perspective and perhaps offering some sense of philosophical ease, the exercise will help to identify the behaviors and rules by which individual human beings increase their Darwinian fitness through the manipulation of society. In a phrase, we are searching for the human biogram.… One of the key questions… is to what extent the biogram represents an adaptation of modern cultural life and to what extent it is a phylogenetic vestige. Our civilizations were jerrybuilt around the biogram. How have they been influenced by it? Conversely, how much flexibility is there in the biogram, and in which parameters particularly? Experience with other animals indicates that when organs are hypertrophied, phylogeny is hard to reconstruct. This is the crux of the problem of the evolutionary analysis of human behavior. [P. 548; emphases mine]
There is much to consider here. “Hypertrophy” suggests an almost unnatural overgrowth of an organ. By what standards do we judge this condition? Do birds have hypertrophied digits? What is the difference between hypertrophy and a complex morphological adaptation? This is really an issue in classification. Wilson uses the term to suggest that humans may have gone too far in one direction and that we are much in need of perspective and self-control. As a biological concept in regard to humans, mental hypertrophy is vacuous.
At the same time that Wilson evokes human variability in ethnicity and in social roles, he darkly invokes a biogram that must necessarily set limits around the protean character of humanity. Biology teaches us, he suggests, what these limits are so we can know how to behave.
Surely this make no sense in view of his general theory. If, as he has insisted throughout the book, he is a biological determinist, then humans cannot behave in any way that is not biologically feasible. If this is the case, what is there to worry about? But Wilson is obviously worried. The true meaning of mental hypertrophy becomes clearer now. He thinks that overdevelopment of the brain can lead us to think and behave in ways that are not consistent with our survival. If we want to survive as a species, we must come back to reality and analyze the true evolutionary constraints that affect us.
Clearly this is a peculiar problem for an evolutionist to worry about. No other species concerns itself with species immortality. Species adapt or not; they continue or become extinct. For all his emphasis on evolution, Wilson finds such a fate intolerable for humanity. We should try to develop the perfect adaptation and become immortal as a species. While the appeal of this view is understandable, it has no conceivable connection to sociobiology and is only tenuously related to evolutionary biology. It is also a view that such thinkers as Malthus, Galton, Lorenz, and Desmond Morris have held without reference to sociobiological theory at all.
After this strange beginning, Wilson deals with human flexibility in more detail. He speaks of “ecological release” through lack of competition with other species (p. 550), and he christens the human capacity for flexible behavior genetic “underprescription” (p. 559). This amounts to a double renaming of what most anthropologists would simply call cultural behavior.
Rudimentary discussions of language, the nuclear family, and other issues show how far out of his own area of expertise Wilson has strayed. These divagations should not be taken too seriously because the real point comes when Wilson tries to sharpen his analysis of culture.
“Culture, including the more resplendent manifestations of ritual and religion, can be interpreted as a hierarchical system of environmental tracking devices” (p. 560). Culture change and environmental change thus occur at similar rates. Religion, however, apparently interferes with such tracking:
Formal religion … has many elements of magic but is focused on deeper, more tribally oriented beliefs. The enduring paradox of religion is that so much of its substance is demonstrably false, yet it remains a driving force in all societies. Men would rather believe than know, have the void as purpose, as Nietzsche said, than be void of purpose.… The individual is prepared by the sacred rituals for supreme effort and self-sacrifice.… Deus vult was the rallying cry of the First Crusade. God wills it, but the summed Darwinian fitness of the tribe was the ultimate if unrecognized beneficiary. [P. 561]
This situation is apparently connected to hypertrophy. Definable evolutionary conditions have led us to mental hypertrophy, which has increased our capacity for flexible behavior. But this flexibility is now hedged round by the irrationalism of religion, which has monopolized the means of indoctrinating people with regard to altruistic behavior. The “demonstrably false” religions are taking our hypertrophy and turning it into a danger for our species. This danger must be met, and the answer is sociobiology:
It seems that our autocatalytic social evolution has locked us onto a particular course which the early hominids still within us may not wel-come. To maintain the species indefinitely we are compelled to drive toward total knowledge, right down to the level of the neuron and gene. When we have progressed enough to explain ourselves in these mechanistic terms, and the social sciences come to full flower, the result might be hard to accept.… But we still have another hundred years. [P. 575; emphases mine]
“To maintain the species indefinitely … total knowledge.” This is Wilson’s true agenda. Our species should strive to maintain itself indefinitely by learning scientifically how evolution applies to us. Thus we must push aside religion and the other “cultural mystifications” that hide what we really are.
This is really an old call to the imposition of rational science over irrational religion on the promise of a utopian future. In this utopia the antithesis between nature and culture will have been abolished by science. The argument assumes that all that is truly human and worthwhile is rational, and that science is thus the quintessence of humanism (as against the false humanism of the so-called humanities). Surely this is the antithesis of the scientific method.
Scientific Method and Loose Thinking
One way of dealing with some of the most patent inconsistencies in Sociobiology is to claim that Wilson is simply a bad scientist, or at least a very naive one. Such a convenient view does not account for the data and is much too easy a way out of a complex problem. Wilson is a famous and widely respected scientist who clearly understands the canons of scientific method. His abstract discussion of the theoretical structure and requirements of sociobiology demonstrates this understanding. He emphasizes a distinction between ultimate and proximate causality, one that is now much bandied about. By “proximate causation” he means essentially such immediately functional causes as anatomy, physiology, and behavior. By “ultimate causation” he means the necessities created by the environment (p. 23). Clearly some such distinction is important in most dynamic analyses and in analyses where differences in scale are important. Yet these distinctions, unless they are carefully handled, are a perfect escape clause that can protect a theory from empirical challenge. If inconvenient evidence is found at one level, then causality at the other level can be invoked, and Wilson does invoke it repeatedly in his human examples.
In the section “Reasoning in Sociobiology” Wilson gives a fair characterization of the deductive basis of science. He discusses the use of “strong inference” and criticizes the “advocacy” method of proof. Arguing in favor of multicausal theories in sociobiology that move the various levels of analysis together in a sensible way, he concludes, “The goal of investigation should not be to advocate the simplest explanation, but rather to enumerate all of the possible explanations, improbable as well as likely, and then to devise tests to eliminate some of them” (p. 30). One can only agree. This is a textbook scientific method. That Wilson is aware of these rules is important because, as we shall see, the requirement to develop a variety of hypotheses, devise tests, and apply them is dropped when his subject is humans.
By Chapter 5 he has moved far from these elegant statements about scientific method. Such comments as the following are found:
Human behavior abounds with reciprocal altruism consistent with genetic theory.… The critical gene frequency is simply that in which playing the game pays by virtue of a high enough probability of contacting another cooperator. The machinery for bringing the gene frequency up to the critical value must lie outside the game itself. It could be genetic drift in small populations… or a concomitant of interdemic or kin selection favoring other aspects of altruism displayed by the cooperator genotypes. [Pp. 120–21]
The method of strong inference is gone, and with it the elaboration of multiple hypotheses and the use of tests to eliminate some. Proofs regarding human behavior in particular hang on the words “consistent with,” a slippery phrase that says “caused by” without really defending or testing the proposition.
Wilson concludes Part I with the following statement:
Although the theory of group selection is still rudimentary, it has already provided insights into some of the least understood and most disturbing qualities of social behavior. Above all, it predicts ambivalence as a way of life in social creatures.… In the opening chapter of this book, I suggested that a science of sociobiology, if coupled with neurophysiology, might transform the insights of ancient religions into a precise account of the evolutionary origin of ethics and hence explain the reasons why we make certain moral choices instead of others at particular times. Whether such understanding will then produce the Rule remains to be seen. For the moment, perhaps it is enough to establish that a single strong thread does indeed run from the conduct of termite colonies and turkey brotherhoods to the social behavior of man. [P. 129; emphasis mine]
Wilson promises that sociobiology can convert religion and morality into science by reducing them to evolutionary theory. This moralized science promises to save humanity by purging culture of its irrational elements and bringing us into concert with the environment through reason. The scientific method and strong inference have been supplanted by the advocacy method. That a “single… thread” runs from termites to man could be true in any typological system (e.g., we both locomote by means of limbs of some sort). The strength of his thread is supplied by the logic of the system he has created, not by any tests he devised or applied. The thread is strong only if we already believe Wilson.
On Human Nature
In writing On Human Nature Wilson had much damage to repair. The book is a great disappointment in this regard. It does, however, confirm my reading of the cultural system that underlies the views expressed in Sociobiology.
On Human Nature is an avowedly speculative view of the union of the natural and the social sciences. We shall see that the terms of union make it an annexation of the latter by the former. Not as compellingly organized as Sociobiology, it adopts a topical approach to aspects of human nature encapsulated in such chapter titles as “Dilemma” and “Hope.” The body of the work contains a disappointing array of observations about humans.
Since the principles of both sociobiology in particular and evolutionary biology in general are suspended in the chapter on humans in Sociobiology, one approaches On Human Nature with hope that this failing will have been at least partly rectified. It has not. Indeed, its contents are indistinguishable from those of popular works by such authors as Lorenz, Ardrey, and Morris.
Sociobiology, given its important new formulations regarding the evolution of social behavior, should make some notable changes at least in the phrasing of evolutionary questions about human behavior. Yet one seeks in vain for new perspectives on human behavior in On Human Nature. The deviations from evolutionary analysis effectively domesticate sociobiology so that it preserves the traditional Western view of human nature while covering it with the terminological trappings of Darwinism.
“Man’s Ultimate Nature,” Natural Reason, and Truth
Chapter 1 opens with this question: “What is man’s ultimate nature?” The question itself betrays the fundamental orientation of the work. What can the “ultimate nature” of a species mean if a species is a congeries of ranges of variation that are continuously shifting? Can we talk about the “ultimate nature” of a species in evolutionary biology? Certainly not. This concept only fits the chain-of-being model of creation. Thus the book begins on a nonevolutionary note.
This question is immediately followed by a statement that distracts our attention from the issues just raised and focuses on the specter of materialism: “If the brain is a machine of ten billion nerve cells and the mind can somehow be explained as the summed activity of a finite number of chemical and electrical reactions, boundaries limit the human prospect—we are biological and our souls cannot fly free” (Wilson 1978:1). This statement introduces a theme that runs throughout the work. Biology is a constraint on culture. To be realistic we must adjust our culture to this fact. Such a view of the relationship between biology and culture is inappropriate to modern biology, but it is common in the works of Hippocrates, Jean Bodin, and other pre-Darwinian writers.
Wilson has a strong tendency to link such concepts as soul with religion and culture, and to link such concepts as science and rationality with transcendence of the limits of culture. Wilson naturalizes reason: “The human mind is a device for survival and reproduction, and reason is just one of its various techniques”; “Human nature can be laid open as an object of fully empirical research, biology can be put to the service of liberal education, and our self-conception can be enormously and truthfully enriched” (p. 2). Reason is natural; natural science is about what is natural; what is natural is real and true. Thus natural science can tell us the truth about ourselves and move our reasoning onto a mature plane, far from the fantasy world of religion and the humanities.
In order to search for a new morality based upon a more truthful definition of man, it is necessary to look inward, to dissect the machinery of the mind and to retrace its evolutionary history. But that effort, I predict, will uncover a second dilemma, which is the choice that must be made among the ethical premises inherent in man’s biological nature. [Pp. 4–5]
Biological Constraints and Moral Choice
According to Sociobiology, we are programmed for both selfishness and altruism. The only moral choice Wilson can understand is between these alternatives. In On Human Nature he eliminates this moral choice by arguing that it is rational to be altruistic. Further, he wants to use biology to prove that after we have measured the tightness of the material constraints, we still have the freedom to choose.
The challenge to science is to measure the tightness of the constraints caused by the programming, to find their source in the brain, and to decode their significance through the reconstruction of the evolutionary history of the mind.… [We will then be able to decide which] of the censors and motivators should be obeyed and which one might better be curtailed or sublimated.… [P. 6]
This is an odd position for an author who begins a book with an epigraph from Hume, who compellingly portrays the distance separating “is” from “ought.”
Wilson really only plays with the idea of constraint. He pretends to measure constraint to prove that we have the freedom to choose, that rationality has a role to play. Yet by annihilating the understanding of cultural systems in both of his books, he deprives that appeal to rationality of any context or meaning.
The question of constraint comes up again in a variety of forms: “The question is no longer whether human social behavior is genetically determined; it is to what extent” (p. 19). It is a serious error to attempt to analyze the relationship between biology and culture as a single continuum ranging from fully biological to fully cultural and then to place traits along the continuum. As Lewontin ([1974] 1976) has argued more powerfully than anyone else, this is bad biology.
All culture is biological, for without biological beings there is no culture. But if we agree that all culture is 100 percent biological in this sense, we have said nothing useful about constraints, freedom, culture, or behavior. Wilson has simply restated the old dichotomies—environment/culture, nature/nurture, genes/culture, constraint/freedom. These polarities do not belong in evolutionary biology.
Wilson confuses the issue further: “Either possibility—complete cultural determination versus shared cultural and genetic determination of variability within the species—is compatible with the more general sociobiological view of human nature” (pp. 42–43). Having started from the position that everything humans do is biological and material, he here argues that some things may be cultural without being biological. This confusion is nothing more than an expression of the old dualistic model of human nature.
Wilson’s quest for the ultimate nature of humans also leads him into trouble with biological diversity. He turns the problem over and over and finally tries the following formulation: “Hope and pride and not despair are the ultimate legacy of genetic diversity, because we are a single species, not two or more.… Mankind viewed over many generations shares a single human nature.…” (p. 50). Whatever this statement means, and I challenge others to make sense of it, it only highlights the problem of trying to assert a species essence in the humoral/environmental sense and biological diversity in an evolutionary biological sense. The positions are irreconcilable.
At the end of the work, Wilson returns to the question of moral choice. Given our ambivalent “essence,” we are biologically programmed to be free to choose between selfishness and altruism. But in his view, science tells us that only altruism is rational. As he puts it, “circularity of the human predicament is not so tight that it cannot be broken through an exercise of will.” Sociobiology “will fashion a biology of ethics, which will make possible the selection of a more deeply understood and enduring code of moral values” (p. 196). Then he provides this biology of ethics:
Because natural selection has acted on the behavior of individuals who benefit themselves and their immediate relatives, human nature bends us to the imperatives of selfishness and tribalism. But a more detached view of the long-range course of evolution should allow us to see beyond the blind decision-making process of natural selection and to envision the history and future of our own genes against the background of the entire human species. A word already in use intuitively defines this view: nobility. Had the dinosaurs grasped the concept they might have survived. They might have been us. [P. 197]
This remarkable passage sums up Wilson’s true agenda. The mental hypertrophy that characterizes humans should allow us to see past selfishness as shortsighted and to realize that altruism, though in the short term possibly disadvantageous, in the long term will ensure our survival. Evolution is blind but it has produced a creature capable of vision. Our will and our reason can permit us to outsmart the environment and approach the ideal of bringing evolution to a halt. We must look to empirical biological research for our ethical systems; we must derive “ought” directly from “is.” The price for failure is ongoing evolution, which may leave us as extinct as the dinosaurs.
Evolutionary “Truth”
In Wilson’s view, what most encumbers our vision is the “falsity” of our cultural systems. Our religious ideas are especially at fault because they supposedly deny the materiality of human life and celebrate the irrational. To address this problem Wilson suggests that we drop the “biblical epic” and put the “evolutionary epic” in its place.
The core of scientific materialism is the evolutionary epic.… What I am suggesting … is that the evolutionary epic is probably the best myth we will ever have. It can be adjusted until it comes as close to truth as the human mind is constructed to judge the truth. And if that is the case, the mythopoeic requirements of the mind must somehow be met by scientific materialism so as to reinvest our superb energies. [P. 201]
Man’s destiny is to know, if only because societies with knowledge culturally dominate societies that lack it. [P. 207]
The problem is that our cultural knowledge thus far in human history has been “false.” Now we can make it “true.”
What is the truth? It appears that the truth is that a judicious combination of selfishness and altruism is the only evolutionary strategy that will work. This is universally true no matter what the circumstances or time period. Under these conditions, the only moral thing to do is to follow the dictates of scientific reasoning, which has uncovered the universal and eternally best strategy for survival. Thus Wilson ends by spiritualizing biological science, trying to convert its results into direct guidelines for behavior based on the analysis of the diversity of species now existing and their evolutionary histories.
Genes, Mind, and Culture
In collaboration with the physicist Charles Lumsden, Wilson has made yet another attempt to deal with humans in a way that is supposed to be sociobiological. To Wilson’s credit, he not only keeps trying to strengthen his position but also recognizes basically where the difficulties in the enterprise lie. The relationship of the genetic, mental, and cultural components of human behavior has been the central difficulty, and Genes, Mind, and Culture (Lumsden and Wilson 1981) deals directly with this problem.
As in the case of On Human Nature, one reads this book in the hope that the enormous amount of criticism leveled at Wilson’s two earlier works will have significantly sharpened his formulation. Despite an improved lexicon, a complex statistical apparatus, and wider reading in cultural anthropology, Wilson has become so entangled in the difficulties already described that he has moved away from rather than toward his goal.
In the Preface Lumsden and Wilson argue that genetic and cultural evolution must be linked, and that the connection between them may be found in “the ontogenetic development of mental activity and behavior” (Lumsden and Wilson 1981:ix). This argument is coupled with a criticism of sociobiology for having failed to deal successfully with the operations of the human mind and with the immense amount of cultural diversity found even in the contemporary human world. This is an encouraging beginning.
The Introduction contains virtually unexceptionable statements about the necessary relationship between genes and culture: “We view it … as a largely unknown evolutionary process—a complicated, fascinating interaction in which culture is generated and shaped by biological imperatives while biological traits are simultaneously altered by genetic evolution in response to cultural innovation” (p. 1).
Except for the use of the indefensible term “cultural evolution” (a fault the authors share with most other practitioners in this field),2 this reasoning makes sense. No doubt there must be a relationship between genes and culture. Conceptualizing it as a complex, interactive process seems currently the most promising way to move the discussion. Yet within a few pages the authors manage to extinguish all enthusiasm for their approach by returning to the contradictions that flawed Wilson’s previous works.
Early on we are faced with the possibility of “pure cultural evolution,” which is somehow dependent on genetic controls. The conceptualization of the relationship between genes and culture is as confused as ever. Once again Wilson views the relationship between genes and culture as one in which genes hold culture “on a leash” (now called the “leash principle” [p. 13]). Most of the book is devoted to mathematical estimates of the varying length of the leash.
Without genes there is no culture. Yet genes hold culture on a leash. The incompatibility of these two views is clear. If we argue, as we must, that without genes there is no culture, then the only reasonable idiom for discussing the relationship between genes and culture is one involving the analysis of the relationship between levels of causation, perhaps in the general systems mode. But if we follow this course, it makes no sense to say that genes hold culture on a leash. The leash principle asserts that there is one entity in the world to be called “genes” and another to be called “culture,” and that the degree to which the former ordains the details of the latter is determined by the length of the leash between them. The leash principle reproduces the old nature/culture argument while the idea that there is no culture without genes demolishes the distinction.
Because this approach is deeply wound into the internal structure of the work, it compromises the rest of Genes, Mind, and Culture. Culture is treated as an adaptive system without reference to the problem of meaning. The mind remains a fitness-informing device concerned with survival and reproduction; and evolution is again treated as a myth that is powerful only because it is “true.”
Wilson still recoils from the notion that the apparent complexity of human sociocultural arrangements must be taken seriously rather than reduced to a few homilistic rules. “Although Homo sapiens is the most complex species on earth by a spectacular margin, it is probably far less complex and difficult to understand than contemporary social theory leads one to believe” (p. 350).
He then takes aim at hermeneutics as a kind of obscurantist philosophy designed to descend into an antiscientific universe of cultural details. He tips his hat to Marx’s attempt to formulate the laws of history, saying that the effort was a good one that now can be carried forward with the help of sociobiology. And the book closes roughly where Sociobiology closed, all the evocations of interactive biocultural processes and of cultural complexity having produced no substantial effect. No more convincing display of the power of culture to invoke and maintain meanings can be found than Wilson’s own derailment of evolutionary biology in the service of his nonevolutionary view of the relationship between nature and culture.
Wilson as an Evolutionist
It is clear that when Wilson deals with humans, he uses neither sociobiology nor evolutionism. Rather he is a naturalistic thinker in the tradition of those whose ideas rest on a dichotomous static vision of nature and culture. Except for the occasional loose connection made between kin selection, reciprocal altruism, and cooperative behavior, Wilson is content to use biological information to make the case that we humans are in grave danger of extinguishing ourselves because of the contradictions in our “nature.”
Most of the major rules of evolutionary biology are overturned. Despite some remarks here and there about diversity in human populations, Wilson speaks of humans as having a “nature,” indeed as having an “ultimate nature” that is potentially permanent. Nothing in evolutionism permits such assertions. A species is an interbreeding congeries of varying traits, continually in motion, with fuzzy boundaries in fact, if not by definition.
Wilson’s goal is to preserve our species from extinction by perfecting our ecological release via proper balancing of our selfish and altruistic natures. While the goal of preservation of our species may be laudable, nothing in evolutionary biology justifies such actions. Evolutionary biology is not about preserving species indefinitely; it is about the mechanisms and trajectories of evolutionary change.
In the most bald fashion, Wilson repeatedly moves from what he considers to be the facts of evolutionary biology to the moral imperatives he thinks we must follow. He leaps across the boundary from “is” to “ought” without regard for most thinkers’ belief that such a leap is rationally unjustifiable and ideologically compromised. He thinks that a philosophy of empiricism will simply and directly solve our moral dilemmas.
This belief finds no support in evolutionary biology. Evolution is a theory, not a description of neutral facts. Evolutionary theory produces no clear moral imperatives. We may weigh the evolutionary consequences that can arise from various courses of action, but the choice of a course of action and the imposition of that choice on others in our society cannot be justified on simple evolutionary grounds.
Wilson’s pattern of thought is not explicable in terms of evolutionary theory but it does fit the old Western view of the human epic. Humans began in a state of nature in which natural laws virtually controlled all. As we became increasingly successful and proliferated, our cultural ideas became more and more complex, obscuring the “real” (natural) requirements of human existence. We began to act in ways not in our collective interest. But this dangerous cultural world also gave rise to the scientific method, and its advance ushered in the possiblity of a final age of human evolution in which scientific purging of untrue cultural ideas will permit us self-consciously (rationally) to regulate our relationships with nature, using reason to abolish the contradiction between nature and culture. This is an elite-managed rational utopia.
While a knowledge of evolutionary biology does not help us understand what Wilson thinks, an understanding of medieval theories about the relationship between purity of blood and social order does. The genealogical principle dominates in those theories, and blood “holds culture on a leash”; the social order is a reflection of the biological characteristics of the population. Environmental and historical effects, such as invasions and migrations, have confused the relations between blood and social position. As a result, a scientific analytical effort is necessary for effective political management and responsible moral judgment.
Social order depends on obedience to these basic “natural” principles. “Science” served this medieval enterprise in the form of elaborate genealogical investigations to determine the “natural” constraints involved. Politics and ethics were felt to be the direct expressions of rational inquiry. History was viewed as the playing out of these natural principles. Once the principles were understood, history became an intelligible, manageable process.
The claim that Wilson’s construal of the relationship between nature and culture has much in common with arguments about purity of blood is not made with the intention of ridiculing Wilson. He is a sincere and serious scholar and deserves to be treated as such. Rather it emphasizes the fundamental similarity between his views and those pre-evolutionary views in reifying the distinction between nature and culture as a way of harnessing science to political and moral judgment.
What then is sociobiological or evolutionary about Wilson’s view of humans? Nothing. Wilson’s human sociobiology has been fully domesticated by an ancient Western cultural vision. That his own view of human nature cannot explain analytically the power and permanence of the very cultural visions of which he is captive is the strongest reason to reject what he says.
Lest it be thought that Wilson is singled out for particular abuse, I must point out that Wilson’s opponents often argue in ways that differ little from his. As is commonplace in attacks on biological determinist views such as Wilson’s, some opponents take such extreme counterpositions that they end up arguing from supposed “facts of nature” to their own particular political and ethical preferences.
One of many egregious examples in the antisociobiological literature is the Sociobiology Study Group’s “Sociobiology: A New Biological Determinism” (1977). After offering theoretical and empirical criticisms of Wilson’s views—all perfectly legitimate and powerful—they argue that there can be no evidence for sociobiology because “the truth is that the individual’s social activity is to be understood only by first understanding social institutions … we know of no relevent [sic] constraints placed on social processes by human biology” (p. 148; emphasis mine). This mode of argument mirrors Wilson’s advocacy view. The Sociobiology Study Group’s “scientific facts” about humans are turned into direct support for their own political and ethical scheme. This logic is as unacceptable in the Sociobiology Study Group as it is in Wilson. Both sides are guilty of attempting to create the illusion that science supports their politics and ethics.
Does this mean that human sociobiology is an enterprise devoid of merit? The very criticisms I have made force rejection of this claim. Since Wilson’s approach to humans is nonevolutionary, a rejection of Wilson does not entitle us to reject human sociobiology. Whatever the possibilities of human sociobiology are, Wilson does not explore them in an evolutionary way. Thus my argument is not about the truth or falsity of human sociobiology; it is an explanation of the cultural forces at work that have led a major evolutionary biologist to reject much of the evolutionary paradigm when he deals with humans, that have made many of his critics equally antievolutionary, and that have led both to resemble medieval thinkers theorizing about the relationship between blood and social order. The genealogical principle, the environmental principle, and the static categories of species in the world, albeit in modified form, are still powerfully present, along with their political and moral accompaniments.